- The Uncertainty Project
- Posts
- đŽ Uncertainty as Doubt (Part 1)
đŽ Uncertainty as Doubt (Part 1)
A two-part tour through Amar Bhide's "Uncertainty and Enterprise"
Good morning!
At the Uncertainty Project, we explore models and techniques for managing uncertainty, decision making, and strategy. Every week we package up our learnings and share them with the 2,000+ leaders like you that read this newsletter!
This week and next we build on the learnings from John Kay and Mervyn Kingâs âRadical Uncertaintyâ with a review of ideas from Amar Bhideâs âUncertainty and Enterpriseâ.

It is surprisingly difficult to craft a definition of uncertainty.
Because of that, it is illuminating to study how different definitions were formed, changed, and debated over time.
This week and next, weâll take a tour of how uncertainty, as a concept in business, over the last 100 years. Our tour guide will be professor Amar Bhide, who has taught at leading business schools over his long career. His recent book âUncertainty and Enterpriseâ does a great job of resurfacing some landmark definitions of uncertainty, describing their evolution through the 20th century, and launching his own effort to pragmatically âmodernizeâ these definitions, for todayâs needs.
His tour begins with a re-introduction of Frank Knight. His article âUncertainty, Risk, and Profitâ (1921) was one of the first to draw a contrast between risk and uncertainty:
Risk can be objectively calculated, from frequencies, historical statistics, or probabilities like a coin toss
Uncertainty is defined by exclusion: things that we cannot measure in these ways
Bhide is interested in how definitions of uncertainty shape the risk-taking in enterprise settings. That was Knightâs interest as well.
They both ask the fundamental question:
For an entrepreneur, âWhere do profits come from?â
âUnique situations force an entrepreneur to form judgments about what will happen. A correct judgment produces profit; a misjudgment, loss.â
These judgments about âwhat will happenâ are made in the presence of uncertainty (per Knightâs definition), not risk. So the use of probabilities, in Knightâs view, was not appropriate.
Years later, Jimmy Savage (now thatâs an all-time great name!) established âsubjective probabilitiesâ, by which an individual can attempt to state a probability about uncertain things âas ifâ they knew the frequencies or historical statistics. This idea seems a little crazy, but it opened the door to a more mathematical approach to modeling uncertainty, in economic circles. This reliance on subjective probabilities became the norm for mainstream economic thinking (and spawned tools like decision trees).
This shift towards the use of subjective probabilities (like with Bayesian Thinking) pushed Knight into the background of mainstream economic theory.
Bhide thinks he deserves a second look.
Bhide describes his efforts in the book as a âmodernization projectâ for Knightâs work - driving a shift from treating uncertainty as the absence of historical frequencies (per Knight) to treating uncertainty as the mental state of doubt.
The new idea here is that uncertainty could be approached as a personal (âsubjectiveâ) mental state. He argues that uncertainty is âpsychological, located within the individualâ and that Knightâs definition as âsituational uncertaintyâ makes it impossibly objective - and fails to acknowledge that itâs the individual that decides whether something is uncertain.
By shifting the focus to doubts, we change the conversation from âwhat isâ (objective) to âwhat we feel it isâ (subjective), but avoid the crazy reliance on probability. Doubts can emerge from our individual (or collective) ignorance of existing or past conditions, i.e. the âknown unknownsâ. Having doubt is the opposite of having conviction, which is how we (generally) feel in the absence of uncertainty.
Bhide describes how uncertainty is handled in legal circles, to draw a contrast with how it is handled in economics. In economics, general, universal theories are held in the highest regard. In legal settings, itâs more pragmatic, and this offers a clue to better definitions of uncertainty.
He reminds us that âbeyond reasonable doubtâ prosecutions do not remove all possible doubt. But⌠with doubt comes the possibility of error, which is key. As Bhide says, âThe possibility of error raises issues of justification, which are at the heart of my project to update Knight.â
Hereâs an illustration of how evidence (or a lack thereof) can drive us across a spectrum from confidence to doubt. It shows two styles of evidence, echoing Knightâs distinctions between contexts predominately facing risk (shown on the bottom) and uncertainty (shown on the top).

When historical statistics are available (revealing expected frequencies), we talk about how sample sizes might influence our position on the spectrum from confidence to doubt.
When historical statistics are not available (true uncertainty, per Knight), we talk about how pieces of contextual evidence help us build plausible stories about the unknowable future. The volume, quality, and shared understanding around that evidence influences where we position ourselves on the spectrum from confidence to doubt.
So what does it take to reduce our doubts, in the name of reducing uncertainty? Our tour will look at this from several angles:
Agreement - involving other people
Justification - making a case
Evidence - volume, quality, and interpretability
Ambiguity - degree of interpretability
Large Organizations - and their routines (covered next week)
Narratives - two modes, and good form (covered next week)
In general, we seek to reduce our doubts by gaining agreement with others, using narratives that provide justifications based on evidence - that is often steeped in ambiguity. In large organizations, this is often supported by specific routines.
On Agreement
Bhide frames his definition of uncertainty in the âknown unknownsâ, avoiding the existential angst around âunknown unknownsâ (saying those conversations are usually a waste of time).
For the âknown unknownsâ, we are forced to grapple with our doubts about âwhat might beâ. And this grappling is best done with others. He says, âWhere there is doubt, there is the possibility of disagreements.â
Sometimes these disagreements can just be traced back to conflict of interests. But there are also cases in discussions of a âone-offâ decision (e.g. a unique, unprecedented business opportunity), where interests are aligned, and disagreements still emerge.
âDifferences in backgrounds and beliefs can create strong disagreements about one-offs. One-offs require inferences based on generalizations and assumptions. Interpretations of the different information types require different background generalizations. Many of these generalizations are ad-hoc rules of thumb derived from personal experience and idiosyncratic âabductionâ, not well-established scientific rules.â
So when should we expect disagreement?
When information is incomplete
When situations are new or novel
When attitudes and temperament are different
Not every disagreement is worth a fight. But when the stakes matter, it âcan spur efforts and arrangements to reach agreements through justificatory discourse - the giving and taking of plausible reasons.â And - most importantly - it is âthe magnitude of the stakes - the cost of a mistake or misjudgment - (that) affects the conventional demand for justification.â
On Justification
But where do we find the supply for this demand for justification?
We supply it via our routines (i.e. rituals, meetings, messaging threads, hallway conversations).
High stakes decisions drive routines that âembody a high demand for verifiable evidence.â
Crucially, these routines âoften require extended deliberation, not just more evidence.â
When collecting evidence, we face the law of diminishing returns: âThis question of sufficiency - deciding how much evidence is enough and when to stop looking for more - also poses acute challenges.â
Bhide, like Olivier Sibony and the concept of decision architecture, points to organizational routines as the way to address this challenge. On this topic, he does not find much to recommend in mainstream economic theory:
âMy answer unapologetically focuses on âpragmaticâ domain-specific routines that economists and decision theorists often ignore. Here, as in many practical matters, we must manage the problems of relevance and sufficiency without much guidance from a general theory.â
Instead, he recommends following the pragmatism of Herbert Simon, and his idea of âsatisficingâ.
On Evidence
A few weeks ago we shared John Kay and Mervyn Kingâs take on the impossibility of building complete decision trees.
Herbert Simon (who we discussed here last year) felt the same way above this chasm between the theory and our actual behaviors.
In general, Simon âregarded businesses and other organizations as âmachinery for coping with the limits of manâs abilities to comprehend and compute in the face of complexity and uncertainty.ââ. Now, thatâs a solid definition!
Bhide describes what led to Simonâs concept of âsatisficingâ, which is his alternative to optimizing around utility- or profit-maximization:
âStandard global rationality required calculating all possible payoffs. But there was no evidence that âin actual human choice situations of any complexity, these computations can be, or are in fact, performed.â Actual decision making, therefore, required simplification.â
Simon proposed that the simplification occurred thus: âIf the alternatives for choice are not given initially to the decision maker, then [s]he must search for them.â And as with evidentiary weight accumulation⌠(this) searching requires rules for stopping. But someone who starts searching because she does not know what alternatives are available cannot know when she has found the best possible one.
Simon proposed a simple rule: Evaluate alternatives against an aspiration level, not an unknowable maximizing standard. When an alternative âsatisfiesâ the aspiration, stop; otherwise, continue searching.â
[As a side note: This emphasis on setting aspirations to guide an exploration of a possibility space is similar to how Roger Martin starts his âStrategy Cascadeâ with a definition of a âwinning aspiration.â ]
Simon also built organizational theories that envisioned organizational procedures for dealing with the âsocial-psychological factorsâ could impede decision making, like:
Replacing global profit-maximizing goals with satisficing subgoals
Dividing the decision-making task among many specialists
Coordinating the work of these specialists by means of a structure of communications and authority relations
In Simonâs view, an organization should strive to decentralize the decision making, and aim for solutions (and levels of evidence) that are âsatisficingâ, not optimized:
âStandard procedures - in legal trials, diagnostic medical protocols, reviews of mortgage applications, and employment reference checks - require efforts to secure satisfactorily complete information. Although they vary in the extent of their uncertainty aversion (and never expect totally complete information), the routines are certainly not uncertainty-neutral.â
This point - that most economic models claim to be âuncertainty-neutralâ - is what drives Bhide up the wall. He is less agitated by the challenges of building a complete decision tree (unlike Kay and King) but more frustrated that these economic theories continue to pretend that uncertainty does not exist.
âHow much omniscience does utility-maximizing behavior require? Plausibly, mainstream theory merely demands âpractical omniscienceâ... Theoretically rational decision-makers donât have to be oblivious to the incompleteness of their information. They can maximize based on what they know, cooly treating what they do not as âneutralâ noise.â
So while these mainstream economic theories claim to be âuncertainty-neutralâ, Bhide is pushing for being more than just âneutralâ.
On Ambiguity
Next (as if defining uncertainty wasnât hard enough), we find ourselves having to talk about the uncertainty-surrounding-the-evidence-we-collect-to-reduce-the-uncertainty!
This is where the concept of ambiguity has been introduced. Bhide summarizes the leading thinkers on this topic:
Daniel Ellsberg defined ambiguity as the âquality depending on the amount, type, reliability, and âunanimityâ of information, giving rise to oneâs degree of âconfidenceâ in an estimate of relative likelihoods.â
Colin Camerer says it surfaces when we are âknown-to-be-missing information, or not knowing relevant information, that could be known.â
Bhide notes that, âMost decision theorists today consider ambiguity as a synonym for uncertainty. A minority, however, maintain that âfundamental uncertainty pertains to situations in which information does not exist at the time of a decision, while ambiguity refers to missing information that could be known.â
And known-to-be-missing information has psychological ramifications. Ellsberg said, âNot knowing important informationâ can be âupsetting and scaryâ making âpeople shy away from taking either side of a bet.â This fear is what leads them to drag their feet when trying to establish their subjective probabilities.
The psychological ramifications extend to innate qualities from person to person. Consider the stereotypical differences between an entrepreneur and a banker:
âDifferences in attitudes towards missing information can hinder joint activity even when there are no differences in information or interests. The same missing information that excites an entrepreneur may repulse potential financiers. Whatâs more, aligning financial incentives cannot close this psychological/behavioral gap: it requires reducing the amount of missing information, either naturally with time, or by securing more information.â
The key point here is that collecting evidence (usually) wonât be enough to remove doubt, in a business setting. Since doubt is personal, we will bring all of our idiosyncratic selves (and our assumptions about the world) into a group conversation about this unknowable future (and the one-off decisions that chart our path into it):
âDoubts about one-offs cannot however be reduced or resolved just through contextual information. Inferences from specific facts typically also require generalizations and assumptions.â
People are messy. And more people, more mess.
Next week (in Part 2), we will finish this conversation by considering how the context changes when people are part of larger organizations, and exploring how organizational routines, when they lean into narratives, can cut through the mess.
Have a great week!

How was this week's post?We'd love to know what you think! (click one) |
Reply